Daniel's topic brings to mind a song about forgiveness by Don Henley called "Heart of the Matter," and so, as a bonus, I include here a video of Henley performing that song live with the Eagles. Daniel's essay follows below.
Background Note
I will be assuming the view
of forgiveness that philosopher Jeffrie Murphy holds, where forgiveness is “the
overcoming, on moral grounds, of what I will call the vindictive passions --
the passions of anger, resentment, and even hatred that are often occasioned
when one has been deeply wronged by another.”
Forgiveness and
Repentance: Some Thoughts
Murphy and Charles Griswold
see a close connection between forgiveness and repentance. Murphy thinks it is
reasonable to condition forgiveness on the wrongdoer’s repentance, while
Griswold takes it that the notion of forgiveness is conceptually tied to
repentance such that if there is no repentance (or at least the willingness to
repent) by the wrongdoer, there is no forgiveness.
Murphy claims that making
forgiveness depend on the wrongdoer’s repentance can guard against “sacrificing
our self-respect or our respect for the moral order -- a respect that is often
evinced in resentment and other vindictive passions.” According to him,
“hastily forgiving” the wrongdoer may condone his or her action(s) and the
degrading message conveyed by it. Withholding forgiveness until repentance can
not only guard one against the harm of not showing self-respect, it can also
give the wrongdoer an incentive for “moral rebirth.” Likewise, Griswold warns that unconditional
forgiveness may condone or encourage wrongdoing, as well as damage victims’
self-respect.
I disagree. First, it seem to
me that there are counterexamples to this view. Consider, for example, the
priest who preemptively forgives Jean Valjean in Les Misérables. His act
seems to me to be both legitimate forgiveness and not any less morally
praiseworthy than an act of forgiveness done in response to repentance. I can
also think of instances in my own life where (I take it) I have genuinely and
rightly forgiven people despite their not repenting.
Second, and in continuation
of this thought, there seems to me to be a variety of morally justifying
grounds for forgiveness that do not require repentance. Consider these examples: God might command unconditional forgiveness;
forgiveness might help realize various goods in the wake of wrongdoing (such as
peace and the avoidance of cycles of revenge); forgiveness without repentance
may be necessary for the thriving, or perhaps even the possibility, of valuable
close relationships; and unconditional forgiveness could motivate moral reform
in the wrongdoer (as it apparently did with Jean Valjean). I do not take this
list to be exhaustive, but offer it as a selection of examples.
Moreover, it is not obvious
to me that unconditional forgiveness sacrifices one’s self-respect or respect
for the moral order. It seems entirely possible to conceive of oneself as having
inherent value and conceive of the wrong done to one as really wrong despite
unconditionally forgiving. The beliefs that “I have inherent value” and “What
person X did to me was wrong” and even “I am entitled to resentment/anger
towards person X for wronging me” seem compatible with the belief that “I
forgive person X (for reason Y)”. Moreover, belief in one’s inherent value and respect
for the moral order can be expressed in ways other than appropriate
vindictiveness, such as deep sadness over what was done (which I take to be
consistent with forgiveness) or verbal repudiation (unless this is an act of
revenge).
In addition, Murphy himself
outlines how a Christian worldview can furnish one with a conceptual framework
that can guard against a loss of self-respect and respect for the moral order
while unconditionally forgiving. Consider
two points he makes. First, on the
Christian view God will see to it that the moral calculus of the universe is
not ultimately out of balance. This, he says, can help one to “relax a bit the
clinch-fisted anger and resentment with which [one tries] to sustain [one’s]
self-respect and hold [one’s] world together all alone.” Second, on the Christian
view we are all loved by God and all created with inherent value as God’s
image-bearers. A firm commitment to these claims can shore up one’s
self-respect regardless of what is done to one.
It is also not obvious that unconditional
forgiveness risks condoning or encouraging wrongs. After all, the claim that
“You did something wrong and inexcusable to me” seems necessarily implicit in
the assertion that “I forgive you.” If
the wrong were excusable, then it would be excused, not forgiven. As
Murphy points out, excusing, unlike forgiveness, is a response to non-culpable
wrongdoing. Forgiveness, on the
other hand, responds to culpable wrongdoing. So, to communicate to someone that they have
been forgiven is necessarily to communicate to that person that they did
something wrong and are culpable for it. So forgiving doesn’t condone or encourage wrongs.
Moreover, there are ways to
discourage wrongdoing while at the same time unconditionally forgiving the
perpetrators. One might do so by way of verbal
repudiation, or by setting an example of virtuous character. One might also discourage wrongdoing by refusing
reconciliation under certain conditions, such as when responding to a
perpetually adulterous spouse, perhaps.
The act of forgiveness itself in these situations may nonetheless so move
the unrepentant wrongdoer as to encourage or bring about moral reform.
All that being said, if
unconditional forgiveness does risk condoning or encouraging wrongs, it is not necessarily
to be faulted on that account. The pursuit or attainment of some goods often
comes at the expense of other goods. For example, to choose to become a surgeon
may mean forfeiting becoming a pastor. Similarly, spending more time with
family can entail spending less time with friends. If unconditionally forgiving in some
circumstances likewise entails risking being seen as condoning or encouraging
wrongs, I think it can be worth taking that risk.
I conclude that we can have forgiveness without repentance. Such forgiveness can be justified for all sorts of reasons; it need not have the costs attributed to it by Murphy and Griswold; and even if it does, the benefits could outweigh those costs.
No comments:
Post a Comment